Contrite Strategies and The Need For Standards

Epistemic Status: Confident

There’s a really interesting paper from 1996 called The Logic of Contrition, which I’ll summarize here.  In it, the authors identify a strategy called “Contrite Tit For Tat”, which does better than either Pavlov or Generous Tit For Tat in Iterated Prisoner’s Dilemma.

In Contrite Tit For Tat, the player doesn’t only look at what he and the other player played on the last term, but also another variable, the standing of the players, which can be good or bad.

If Bob defected on Alice last round but Alice was in good standing, then Bob’s standing switches to bad, and Alice defects against Bob.

If Bob defected on Alice last round but Alice was in bad standing, then Bob’s standing stays good, and Alice cooperates with Bob.

If Bob cooperated with Alice last round, Bob keeps his good standing, and Alice cooperates.

This allows two Contrite Tit For Tat players to recover quickly from accidental defections without defecting against each other forever;

D/C -> C/D -> C/C

But, unlike Pavlov, it consistently resists the “always defect” strategy

D/C -> D/D -> D/D -> D/D …

Like TFT (Tit For Tat) and unlike Pavlov and gTFT (Generous Tit For Tat), cTFT (Contrite Tit For Tat) can invade a population of all Defectors.

A related contrite strategy is Remorse.  Remorse cooperates only if it is in bad standing, or if both players cooperated in the previous round. In other words, Remorse is more aggressive; unlike cTFT, it can attack cooperators.

Against the strategy “always cooperate”, cTFT always cooperates but Remorse alternates cooperating and defecting:

C/C -> C/D -> C/C -> C/D …

And Remorse defends effectively against defectors:

D/C -> D/D -> D/D -> D/D…

But if one Remorse accidentally defects against another, recovery is more difficult:

C/D -> D/C -> D/D -> C/D -> …

If the Prisoner’s Dilemma is repeated a large but finite number of times, cTFT is an evolutionarily stable state in the sense that you can’t do better for yourself when playing against a cTFT player through doing anything that deviates from what cTFT would recommend. This implies that no other strategy can successfully invade a population of all cTFT’s.

REMORSE can sometimes be invaded by strategies better at cooperating with themselves, while Pavlov can sometimes be invaded by Defectors, depending on the payoff matrix; but for all Prisoner’s Dilemma payoff matrices, cTFT resists invasion.

Defector and a similar strategy called Grim Trigger (if a player ever defects on you, keep defecting forever) are evolutionarily stable, but not good outcomes — they result in much lower scores for everyone in the population than TFT or its variants.  By contrast, a whole population that adopts cTFT, gTFT, Pavlov, or Remorse on average gets the payoff from cooperating each round.

The bottom line is, adding “contrition” to TFT makes it quite a bit better, and allows it to keep pace with Pavlov in exploiting TFT’s, while doing better than Pavlov at exploiting Defectors.

This is no longer true if we add noise in the perception of good or bad standing; contrite strategies, like TFT, can get stuck defecting against each other if they erroneously perceive bad standing.

The moral of the story is that there’s a game-theoretic advantage to not only having reciprocity (TFT) but standards (cTFT), and in fact reciprocity alone is not enough to outperform strategies like Pavlov which don’t map well to human moral maxims.

What do I mean by standards?

There’s a difference between saying “Behavior X is better than behavior Y” and saying “Behavior Y is unacceptable.”

The concept of “unacceptable” behavior functions like the concept of “standing” in the game theory paper.  If I do something “unacceptable” and you respond in some negative way (you get mad or punish me or w/e), I’m not supposed to retaliate against your negative response, I’m supposed to accept it.

Pure reciprocity results in blood feuds — “if you kill one of my family I’ll kill one of yours” is perfectly sound Tit For Tat reasoning, but it means that we can’t stop killing once we’ve started.

Arbitrary forgiveness fixes that problem and allows parties to reconcile even if they’ve been fighting, but introduces the new problem that now you’re vulnerable to an attacker who just won’t quit.

Contrite strategies are like having a court system. (Though not an enforcement system!  They are still “anarchist” in that sense — all cTFT bots are equal.)  The “standing” is an assessment attached to each person of whether they are in the wrong and thereby restricted in their permission to retaliate.

In general, for actions not covered by the legal system and even for some that are, we don’t have widely shared standards of acceptable vs. unacceptable behavior.  We’re aware (and especially so given the internet) that these standards differ from subculture to subculture and context to context, and we’re often aware that they’re arbitrary, and so we have enormous difficulty getting widely shared clarity on claims like “he was deceptive and that’s not OK”.  Because…was he deceptive in a way that counts as fraud? Was it just “puffery” of the kind that’s normal in PR?  Was it a white lie to spare someone’s feelings?  Was it “just venting” and thus not expected to be as nuanced or fact-checked as more formal speech?  What level or standard of honesty could he reasonably have been expected to be living up to?

We can’t say “that’s not OK” without some kind of understanding that he had failed to live up to a shared expectation.  And where is that bar?  It’s going to depend who you ask and what local context they’re living in.  And not only that, but the fact that nobody is keeping track of where even the separate, local standards are, eventually standards will have to be dropped to the lowest common denominator if not made explicit.

MBTI isn’t science but it’s illustrative descriptively, and it seems to me that the difference between “Perceivers” and “Judgers”, which is basically the difference between the kinds of people who get called “judgmental” in ordinary English and the people who don’t, is that “Judgers” have a clear idea of where the line is between “acceptable” and “unacceptable” behavior, while Perceivers don’t.  I’m a Perceiver, and I’ve often had this experience where someone is saying “that’s just Not OK” and I’m like “whoa, where are you getting that? I can certainly see that it’s suboptimal, this other thing would be better, but why are you drawing the line for acceptability here instead of somewhere else?”

The lesson of cTFT is that having a line in the first place, having a standard that you can either be in line with or in violation of, has survival value.

 

Advertisements

9 thoughts on “Contrite Strategies and The Need For Standards

  1. The last two posts are some quality IFS work. Many of our parts are feral by default and need to learn how to cooperate (from first principles) to achieve higher order goals. The internal ceasefire is an unimaginable boon to people who haven’t experienced it since childhood. It’s very hard to spend time repairing infrastructure in wartime.

    The thing we’re built on (multicellular life) is an inconceivably vast cooperation architecture. The thing we live within (enlightenment civilization) is an inconceivably vast cooperation architecture. And people/parts wander around thinking they’re clever little shits for having figured out just the right level of abstraction to defect on.
    Or another frame: the seemingly spontaneous interest in such things is a memo ‘Dear system 2, cut the crap. You’re only fooling yourself. Love, system 1.’

    • spontaneous, it ain’t. This is the consequence of me dealing with political stuff and getting to the point where i just want to understand fundamentals first.

      • So, addressing the political side more directly–

        I’ve been thinking, ever since I read the “Feud Law” chapter in Legal Systems Very Different From Ours, is that a big problem right now is a lack of clarity as to what actions are and are not intended as sanctioned retaliation. I mean, OK, a lot of things are covered by the existing legal system and so there’s no big problem there, but there are some places the law can’t or won’t go. Note that of course here I’m referring not just to actual violence but more generally to “fighting”, just trying to crush the other side rather than reason with, negotiate with, or tolerate them.

        It’s clear that a lot of this occurring currently is seen by its perpetrators as justified retaliation — but there’s a failure to make that justification explicit. I mean, OK, they may say it, but not explicitly enough, and often being sufficiently explicit is impossible as it’s just retaliation for general conduct rather than for a specific act. In short, there’s a real lack of clarity. My personal suspicion is that we’d all be better off if people knew about the concept of feud law, and attempted to follow it, in those places the law can’t help. As in, you don’t just retaliate — you make an explicit demand for recompense, with explicit conditions, retaliate only if the demand is not met, and explicitly state (over and over again, because people are just not going to get it otherwise) that this retaliation is specifically in retaliation for this particular act (and therefore is not itself to be retaliated against). (Normally of course there’s the whole arbitration part, but unfortunately in the cases I’m thinking of no arbitration is really possible. The arbitration, I guess, is that hopefully if you retaliate wrongly, outside forces will step in and punish you for it, but there’s no guarantee of that, especially when we’re living in a context where those outside forces may not have these ideas of feud law in mind.)

        In cases where demanding recompense may not make sense for whatever reason, then sure maybe you could skip directly to the retaliation, but that still wouldn’t look like what we have today, because it would still require much more explicitness about what exactly it is in retaliation for, what exactly the retaliatory act consists of and when it will end, and, again, the fact that this is justified retaliation and is not itself to be retaliated against.

        But, I dunno. It’s possible that without people having an understanding of an idea like feud law none of the above might work. There’s a reason I kept emphasizing explicitness above, and partly that’s because people just aren’t thinking that way already; I imagine that in a context where these ideas were widely known and practiced, you might be able to get away with being slightly (though probably not much) less explicit without just causing a spiral of increasing fighting.

  2. I’ve learned about Pavlov strategies only half an hour ago thanks to your articles, so I hesitate to point out a possible mistake in:
    “But, unlike Pavlov, it consistently resists the “always defect” strategy
    D/C -> D/D -> D/D -> D/D …”
    As I understand it, Pavlov switches strategy on negative result, so it should go: D/C -> D/D -> C/C -> …
    Am I wrong?

    • Pavlov, when encountering a DefectBot, will alternate between cooperating and defecting.
      D/C -> D/D -> D/C -> D/C …
      Pavlov always switches its behavior when another player defects on it; so against a DefectBot, which always defects, Pavlov will alternate between cooperate and defecting.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s